The world it is at war: an open ended ��war on terrorism.��
Leaders across the world have repeated the declaration ad nauseam.
We have been told just as many times that it is a �war like
no other.� The stakes are high. If Osama Bin Laden is to be believed, it is the
�Third World War�; for George W. Bush the war is nothing less than a �fight for
civilization.�
As to whether the alleged terrorist attacks on the United
States on September 11, 2001 were in fact an act of war demanding a military
response, or a criminal act demanding a legal and justice based response is
open to question and debate. Secretary of State Colin Powell�s initial response
suggests that he regarded it more in terms of a crime than an act of war: �you
can be sure that America will deal with this tragedy in a way that brings those
responsible to justice,� he is reputed to have said. But President Bush had
other ideas, later telling journalist Bob Woodward that his immediate reaction
was: �They had declared war on us, and I made up my mind at that moment that we
were going to war.� And thus, we are at war.
The casting of the ��war on terrorism�� as a war fought on
behalf of or for civilization against some less-than-civilized other --
terrorists and their cohorts -- is a significant point that cannot be allowed
to pass unexamined. The image being generated and marketed here is one of a war
between the civilized defenders of everything that civilization represents and
the barbarous terrorists who oppose it and want to tear it down. Right or wrong
this image is not exactly new, and thus the �war on terror� is not exactly a
war like no other. Rather, history and precedents have a lot to tell us about
the present and the conducting of this �war on terror.�
Throughout much of organized human history the peoples,
societies and states of our world have been hierarchically divided on the basis
of their approximation to the ideal of civilization. The most advanced
collectives of peoples, civilized states, sit at the apex of civilizational
hierarchy, those at the polar opposite are said to be not far removed from the
state of nature. Somewhere in between these two poles at various stages of
human and social development are barbarians and even less developed �savage�
peoples. Along with a capacity for socio-political organization and
self-government, means of warfare employed in the crucible of war have long
been regarded as key markers of civilization -- or the absence thereof.
Civilized societies, it is said, adhere to the generally
accepted principles of international law, including the laws of war. By their
very nature barbarians and �savages� are deemed incapable of abiding by such
laws. While terrorists might be capable, they are unwilling to do so. In this
respect they are something akin to modern day �savages�; at least in terms of
their problematic place in the international system and international law. Just
what I mean by modern-day �savages� will be outlined shortly, but it is not the
pejorative term that is sloppily bandied about in much of the rhetoric that has
accompanied the declarations of the ��war on terrorism.��
Even prior to September 11, 2001, terrorism was regarded as
some form of �new barbarism� or contemporary �savage war.� The military
historian, Everett Wheeler, suggests that the �shock of modern terrorism
resembles the outrage of seventeenth or eighteenth century European regulars in
North America when ambushed by Indians who ignored the European rules of the
game.� This comparison urges us to recall the �military horizon,� a figurative
line drawn in the sand to distinguish �civilized� European warfare, which was
supposedly organized, constrained, and chivalrous, from the chaotic nature of
the undisciplined and opportunistic �primitive� warfare practiced by �savages�
and barbarians.
In the tradition of the �savage� war thesis, the contention
is that conventional warfare requires, above all else, open battle and
observance of the rules of war. Terrorism on the other hand, is thought akin to
primitive warfare in that the perpetrators either lack or shun a set of values.
Like the warfare attributed to the �savages� and barbarians found in the
Americas, Australia, Africa, Asia, the Middle East, and even Eurasia,
terrorists avoid open confrontation with regular armed forces, relying instead
on primitive warfare tactics such as hit-and-run surprise attacks and
deception.
In respect to the civilized-savage divide, Wheeler suggests
that in the Western tradition of warfare there is some tension between these
rival norms or modes of war making. But the blanket aerial bombing of Dresden
and the dropping of Atomic bombs on Hiroshima and Nagasaki, to take just two
examples -- which include the targeting of civilians -- would indicate that
this tension is very close to the surface. Or perhaps more accurately, it
further exposes and undermines the much cherished myth of Western chivalry. It
also relies on the problematic exclusion of Europe�s fascists and Nazis from
the Western camp. If there is a tension in the Western mindset when it comes to
choosing between the rival norms of warfare, the nature of the combatants
arrayed against it is a key determining factor.
I will return to the �savage� war thesis momentarily, but
first I want to address the not altogether unrelated notion that the �war on
terrorism� is a war like no other. When political and military leaders struggle
to demonstrate the progress they claim is being made in the �war on terror� and
that �we are winning the war,� more often than not they resort to the tired but
trusted explanation: �It is a war like no other.� In one sense they are right;
it is a war like no other. But every war is a war like no other. At the same
time, in a strange way every war is like every other war (in some respects at
least). In recalling the military horizon and the European conquest of �savage
peoples� around the globe, in the fighting of the �war on terror� there are
some precedents and parallels in the characterization of combatants from
conflicts past.
An equally important question is: Is the �war on terrorism�
really a war at all? If we follow the widely acknowledged criteria set out by
the eighteenth century Swiss philosopher Jean-Jacques Rousseau, then it is
probably not a true war. Rousseau wrote: �War . . . is not a relation between
men, but between states; in war individuals are enemies wholly by chance, not
as men, not even as citizens, but only as soldiers; not as members of their
country, but only as its defenders.� In essence, a state�s enemies can only be
other states, likewise its friends and allies. But Rousseau�s account seems a
bit dated in a time of an open-ended �war on terrorism� in which one of the
protagonists is not a state. Despite appearances and the various claims and
counter-claims being made, this is far from a clear-cut issue, there is more
gray than black and white. The �war on terror� is being fought on the ground;
it is being fought in Afghanistan, but no longer against Afghanistan. It is
being fought in Iraq, but not necessarily against Iraq (if there is still such
a country or nation). And, from time to time, it is being fought in London, and
Madrid, and Bali, and wherever else the �terrorists� choose to turn into a
battlefield.
According to Wheeler, terrorism should be recognized as a
form of warfare, albeit a primitive form of warfare with close connections to
guerilla modes of war. The question of whether terrorism and the concomitant �war
on terror� are truly a war is an important one that goes right to the heart of
the legal status of the combatants and the obligations imposed upon them. The
issue of the legal status of combatants is in turn directly relevant to the
connection of terrorism and guerilla warfare with primitive warfare. From
Ancient Greece and Rome onwards soldiers have been legally defined enemies
accorded certain rights and protection. Those recently adjudged �enemy
combatants,� on the other hand, find themselves in a kind of legal Neverland,
first at Camp X-Ray and then Camp Delta in Guantanamo Bay, Cuba, devoid of the
legal rights and privileges afforded prisoners of war.
One of the critical questions arising out of the �savage�
war thesis is one that was posed by the American jurist Quincy Wright in the wake
of the French bombardment of Damascus in October 1925. Wright asked: �Does
international law require the application of laws of war to people of a
different civilization?� Wright firmly believed so, despite the fact that the
ancient Greeks thought the rules of war inapplicable to barbarians, or that the
Israelites are known to have been especially ruthless in warring with certain
enemy tribes, or that medieval Christendom acted in a similar manner in wars
with infidels.
On the other side of the argument, Eldridge Colby, a captain
in the United States Army, thought Wright missed a critical point; that
civilizational differences exist. They are based, he argued, �on a difference
in methods of waging war and on different doctrines of decency in war. When combatants
and non-combatants are practically identical among a people, and savage or
semi-savage peoples take advantage of this identity to effect ruses, surprises,
and massacres on the �regular� enemies, commanders must attack their problems
in entirely different ways from those in which they proceed against Western
peoples.� Setting aside the dubious point being made here, just one of the
obvious problems with this line of argument is: how can one knowingly take
advantage of something they do not know exists? And even if they do know -- as
today�s �terrorists� do -- does this give the other party the right to turn
their back on a set of laws they claim to abide by and which are held up as a
marker of their civilization. Colby concluded that as �devastation and
annihilation� is the principal method of warfare of �savage tribes,� civilized
Westerners are justified in adopting �more brutal� methods as they go about
devastating and annihilating the uncivilized hordes.
In an address to the nation from Fort Bragg in North
Carolina on June 28, 2005, George W. Bush further underlined the notion that
tactics employed by parties to a conflict reflect their degree of civility: the
civilized supposedly chivalrous and noble; the uncivilized barbarous and
cowardly. President Bush declared: �We see the nature of the enemy in
terrorists who exploded car bombs along a busy shopping street in Baghdad,
including one outside a mosque. We see the nature of the enemy in terrorists
who sent a suicide bomber to a teaching hospital in Mosul. We see the nature of
the enemy in terrorists who behead civilian hostages and broadcast their
atrocities for the world to see. These are savage acts of violence.�
Bush went on to proclaim: �We�re fighting against men with
blind hatred -- and armed with lethal weapons -- who are capable of any
atrocity.� These modern �savages,� like the Amerindians and the Viet Cong
before them, �wear no uniform; they respect no laws of warfare or morality.�
When combined with the mantra that the �war on terror� is a �war like no other�
against an enemy that is �pure evil� and refuses to �fight by the rules,� the
inference is that this war demands tactics and means of warfare that are
necessarily more brutal than might otherwise be employed, possibly even
torture.
Terrorists have indeed committed atrocious and criminal
acts. As have those fighting the �war on terrorismm.� For the former,
atrocities and acts of callousness are prescribed policy. The latter insist
that they are isolated incidents committed by a handful of rogue troops, such
as the shameful events at Abu Ghraib
prison in Iraq. But they still happened and continue to happen. There have also
been many other unsavory incidents and instances, such as widespread �collateral
damage�; enough to suggest that there is something more going on than isolated
incidences of brutality. The point to
be made here is that just because one side, the terrorists, choose to
abandon the rules of fair play, that does not mean that the other party to the
conflict has to follow suit and adopt more brutal and indiscriminate means of
warfare. Let alone resort to torture.
It seems that what is really going on here is that in
response to atrocities or acts of savagery by an alleged uncivilized foe, the
West, in the name of civilization and the battle of good over evil, is seeking
to justify a turn to any means necessary, including more brutal means of
warfare. A war against such an �evil and unscrupulous barbarous enemy� cannot
be won by conventional means; rather we must fight fire with fire -- so the
argument goes. Or at least this is what we try to convince ourselves. But
perhaps it is more the case that those more base instincts and uncivilized
means have been at our disposal and employed by us -- the West -- all along.
History seems to suggest as much. All too regularly we dehumanize our enemy --
the �uncivilized savage� who lacks virtue, chivalry, is beyond the pale
materially and morally -- in order to justify to ourselves the recourse to the
more brutal means we claim to abhor and claim to be antithetical to our very
ideal of Civilization. The dichotomy between the civilized, uniformed,
chivalrous combatant and the opportunistic, treacherous barbarian is a false
one. Perhaps there is something in the argument that all people, fundamentally �good�
people included, are capable of doing bad or evil acts given certain
circumstances. Just as �bad� people are capable of random acts of kindness.
As Immanuel Kant reminds us in Perpetual Peace, �even
some philosophers have praised it [war] as an ennoblement of humanity,
forgetting the pronouncement of the Greek who said, �War is an evil inasmuch as
it produces more wicked men than it takes away.�� We would also do well to take
note of Walter Benjamin�s poignantly made point that �there is no document of
civilization which is not at the same time a document of barbarism.� As with
every other war that has been or will ever be fought, no belligerent has a
monopoly on the barbarism and terror of war. The �war on terror� is no
exception.
Dr
Brett Bowden is a Fellow in the Centre for International Governance and Justice
at the Australian National University. He is the author of �The Empire of
Civilization: A story about making History
and influencing Peoples� (forthcoming). An edited collection of essays, �Terror:
From Tyrannicide to Terrorism in Europe, 1605-2005,� will also be published in
2007.